BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback] | ||
England and Wales High Court (Queen's Bench Division) Decisions |
||
You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> England and Wales High Court (Queen's Bench Division) Decisions >> Kirkegaard v Smith [2019] EWHC 3393 (QB) (11 December 2019) URL: http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWHC/QB/2019/3393.html Cite as: [2019] EWHC 3393 (QB) |
[New search] [Printable PDF version] [Help]
QUEEN'S BENCH DIVISION
MEDIA AND COMMUNICATIONS LIST
Strand, London, WC2A 2LL |
||
B e f o r e :
____________________
Emil Kirkegaard |
Claimant |
|
- and - |
||
Oliver Smith |
Defendant |
____________________
Aled Maclean-Jones (instructed by Debenhams Ottaway Solicitors) for the Defendant
Hearing dates: 26 November 2019
____________________
Crown Copyright ©
The Honourable Mr Justice Julian Knowles:
Introduction
a. whether the words pleaded in [3] of the Particulars of Claim (PoC) bear the meanings pleaded in [4], [9], and [14]; and
b. if so, whether those meanings are defamatory of the Claimant.
The words complained of
"If you merely point out @KirkegaardEmil supports child rape and is a paedophile (by quoting his OWN words) you will get stalked by him. He's a malicious individual and sick creep."
"It's not a right or left issue, but right or wrong: anyone with a moral conscience can see Kirkegaard is a vile human and paedophile."
"Why are you defending a blatant paedophile ?"
"Like I said, it's obvious to anyone, Kirkegaard is a paedophile. This is why all mainstream newspapers described him as either a paedophile-apologist or paedophile".
Legal principles
Determining meaning
"11. The Court's task is to determine the single natural and ordinary meaning of the words complained of, which is the meaning that the hypothetical reasonable reader would understand the words bear. It is well recognised that there is an artificiality in this process because individual readers may understand words in different ways …
12. The following key principles can be distilled from the authorities …
(i) The governing principle is reasonableness.
(ii) The intention of the publisher is irrelevant.
(iii) The hypothetical reasonable reader is not naïve but he is not unduly suspicious. He can read between the lines. He can read in an implication more readily than a lawyer and may indulge in a certain amount of loose thinking but he must be treated as being a man who is not avid for scandal and someone who does not, and should not, select one bad meaning where other non-defamatory meanings are available. A reader who always adopts a bad meaning where a less serious or non-defamatory meaning is available is not reasonable: s/he is avid for scandal. But always to adopt the less derogatory meaning would also be unreasonable: it would be naïve.
(iv) Over-elaborate analysis should be avoided and the court should certainly not take a too literal approach to the task.
(v) Consequently, a judge providing written reasons for conclusions on meaning should not fall into the trap of conducting too detailed an analysis of the various passages relied on by the respective parties.
(vi) Any meaning that emerges as the produce of some strained, or forced, or utterly unreasonable interpretation should be rejected.
(vii) It follows that it is not enough to say that by some person or another the words might be understood in a defamatory sense.
(viii) The publication must be read as a whole, and any 'bane and antidote' taken together. Sometimes, the context will clothe the words in a more serious defamatory meaning (for example the classic "rogues' gallery" case). In other cases, the context will weaken (even extinguish altogether) the defamatory meaning that the words would bear if they were read in isolation (eg, bane and antidote cases).
(ix) In order to determine the natural and ordinary meaning of the statement of which the claimant complains, it is necessary to take into account the context in which it appeared and the mode of publication.
(x) No evidence, beyond publication complained of, is admissible in determining the natural and ordinary meaning.
(xi) The hypothetical reader is taken to be representative of those who would read the publication in question. The court can take judicial notice of facts which are common knowledge, but should beware of reliance on impressionistic assessments of the characteristics of a publication's readership.
(xii) Judges should have regard to the impression the article has made upon them themselves in considering what impact it would have made on the hypothetical reasonable reader.
(xiii) In determining the single meaning, the court is free to choose the correct meaning; it is not bound by the meanings advanced by the parties (save that it cannot find a meaning that is more injurious than the claimant's pleaded meaning)."
13. As to the Chase levels of meaning, see Brown v Bower, [17]:
'They come from the decision of Brooke LJ in Chase v News Group Newspapers Ltd [2003] EMLR 11 [45] in which he identified three types of defamatory allegation: broadly, (1) the claimant is guilty of the act; (2) reasonable grounds to suspect that the claimant is guilty of the act; and (3) grounds to investigate whether the claimant has committed the act. In the lexicon of defamation, these have come to be known as the Chase levels. Reflecting the almost infinite capacity for subtle differences in meaning, they are not a straitjacket forcing the court to select one of these prescribed levels of meaning, but they are a helpful shorthand. In Charman v Orion Publishing Group Ltd, for example, Gray J found a meaning of "cogent grounds to suspect' [58].
…
15. Finally, in relation to this case, it is necessary to have regard to the 'repetition rule' (see Brown v Bower [19]-[32]): namely that where an allegation by a third party is repeated by the defendant, the words must be interpreted by reference to the underlying allegations of fact. Context nevertheless remains critical: Brown v Bower [29]."
"Where a judge has to determine meaning it has been said that the correct approach is to ask himself what overall impression the material made on him and then to check that against the detailed textual arguments put forward by the parties. Hence in Armstrong v Times Newspapers Gray J 'deliberately read the article complained of before reading the parties' respective statements of case or the rival skeleton arguments'."
"Although the Claimant has selected only parts of the Articles for complaint, the Court must ascertain the meaning of these sections in the context of each Article as a whole."
"38. All of this, of course, emphasises that the primary role of the court is to focus on how the ordinary reasonable reader would construe the words. And this highlights the court's duty to step aside from a lawyerly analysis and to inhabit the world of the typical reader of a Facebook post. To fulfil that obligation, the court should be particularly conscious of the context in which the statement was made, and it is to that subject that I now turn.
[…]
40. It may be that the significance of context could have been made more explicitly clear in Jeynes, but it is beyond question that this is a factor of considerable importance. And that the way in which the words are presented is relevant to the interpretation of their meaning - Waterson v Lloyd [2013] EWCA Civ 136; [2013] EMLR 17, para 39.
41. The fact that this was a Facebook post is critical. The advent of the 21st century has brought with it a new class of reader: the social media user. The judge tasked with deciding how a Facebook post or a tweet on Twitter would be interpreted by a social media user must keep in mind the way in which such postings and tweets are made and read."
"16. In this case, there is an issue about hyperlinks. As made clear in Warby J's judgment in Yeo v Times Newspapers Ltd [2015] 1 WLR 971 [87], contextual material relied upon by way of hyperlinks is a matter which, as an exception to the rule that no evidence is admissible when determining the natural and ordinary meaning, can and should be proved by evidence. The Defendant has filed a witness statement from Alex Wilson dated 29 January 2019. In it, Mr Wilson helpfully sets out each Article, with hyperlinks underlined. In respect of each hyperlink, he has exhibited what a reader would have been taken to if s/he had followed the hyperlink.
17. The extent to which hyperlinked material in an article would be read by the ordinary reasonable reader does not admit of a hard and fast rule; it is a matter to be judged on the facts of each case: Falter v Atzmon [2018] EWHC 1728 (QB) [12]-[13]. As with most issues relating to meaning in defamation claims, context is everything."
Statement of fact v expression of opinion
"16 […] when determining whether the words complained of contain allegations of fact or opinion, the Court will be guided by the following points:
(i) The statement must be recognisable as comment, as distinct from an imputation of fact.
(ii) Opinion is something which is or can reasonably be inferred to be a deduction, inference, conclusion, criticism, remark, observation, etc
(iii) The ultimate question is how the word would strike the ordinary reasonable reader. The subject matter and context of the words may be an important indicator of whether they are fact or opinion.
(iv) Some statements which are, by their nature and appearance opinion, are nevertheless treated as statements of fact where, for instance, the opinion implies that a claimant has done something but does not indicate what that something is, i.e. the statement is a bare comment.
(v) Whether an allegation that someone has acted 'dishonestly' or 'criminally' is an allegation of fact or expression of opinion will very much depend upon context. There is no fixed rule that a statement that someone has been dishonest must be treated as an allegation of fact.
17. I would also note here what I said recently in Tinkler v v Ferguson [2018] EWHC 3563 (QB) [37] about implied or inferred expression of opinion:
'… a number of adjectives and adverbs have been inserted into the Claimant's meaning which are not part of the natural and ordinary meaning of the words. They are strained constructions of what is being said in the [publication]. For example, if an individual reader thought that the Claimant's alleged behaviour was 'selfish', that would be a personal judgment made by the individual reader. It is neither stated nor implied in the text. Such inferential meanings (that depend upon - and vary between - each individual reader's moral judgment) are not part of the natural and ordinary meaning of words: Brown v Bower [54]. In context, a suggestion that the conduct of the Claimant was 'selfish' would be an expression of an opinion. If such an opinion is expressly stated by the author, then it can readily be identified as such by readers. I find the notion of an 'inferred opinion' conceptually difficult. I suppose it is conceivable that an article may not make express an author's view, but it nevertheless emerges clearly as a result of discernible indications in the text as to what his or her opinion actually is on the given facts. But this is very subjective; and it may be difficult to separate out those cases from cases where what is really happening is simply that the reader is supplying his or her own judgment on the stated facts rather than detecting the author's opinion by implication."
"When a meaning is determined, the Court will have to consider whether the meaning is a statement of fact or opinion. Opinion must be recognisable as an opinion, as distinct from an imputation of fact. The opinion must explicitly or implicitly indicate, at least in general terms, what are the facts on which the opinion is formed, otherwise the opinion will be treated as a statement of fact. It has been said that the sense of opinion 'is something which is or can reasonably be inferred to be a deduction, inference, conclusion, criticism, remark, observation, etc', see Branson v Bower [2001] EWCA Civ 791; [2001] EMLR 32 at paragraph 12 and the authorities there considered. A statement may be fact or opinion, depending on context."
"26. I think that some caution must be applied before overly prescriptive rules are adopted as to the assessment of fact or opinion. The pitfalls of doing so are perhaps demonstrated by Singh. In my judgment, what Eady J is saying in those passages is that context is likely to play a critical role in this assessment. It is the fourth point from Morgan about bare comment. There is no fixed rule that a statement that someone has been dishonest must be treated as an allegation of fact. The real question is whether, in context, the allegation of dishonesty would be understood to be the deduction or inference of the speaker. In most cases, it will be the context in which the words appear or are spoken that will provide the answer to whether the words are (or would be understood to be) opinion or whether the statement is 'bare comment' and therefore potentially liable to be treated as an allegation of fact. Asking a question of whether the statement is 'verifiable' is perhaps a dangerous gloss on this approach.
27 Indeed, I note from Eady J's decision in Lowe v Associated Newspapers Ltd [2007] QB 580, he said this in relation to the test:
'55 …readers need to be able to distinguish facts from comment for the defendant to be permitted to rely upon the defence of fair comment. A bald comment, made in circumstances where it is not possible to understand it as an inference, it is likely to be treated as an assertion of fact which will only be susceptible to a defence of justification or privilege.
56. Where facts are set out in the words complained of, so that the reader can see that an inference or opinion is based upon them, then the defence of fair comment will be available; but the defendant is not tied to the facts stated in the article. He may invite the jury to take into account extrinsic facts 'known to the writer' as part of the material on which they are to decide whether a person could honestly express the opinion or draw the inference.
57. Whilst it is necessary for readers to distinguish fact from comment, it is not necessary for them to have before them all the facts upon which the comment was based for the purpose of deciding whether they agree with the comment (or inference). I draw that conclusion with all due diffidence, since Lord Nicholls has twice expressed the opposite view, but it does seem consistent with principle and, in particular, with the undoubted rule that people are free to express perverse and shocking opinions and may nevertheless succeed in a defence of fair comment without having to persuade reasonable readers, or the jurors who represent such persons, to concur with the opinions. It is difficult to see why it should matter whether a reader agrees; what matters is whether he or she can distinguish fact from comment. Sometimes that will be possible, as it was in Kemsley v Foot , without any facts being stated expressly, because either they are referred to or they are sufficiently widely known for the readers to recognise the comment as comment.'
"18. … Where hyperlinks are provided in an online article, there is no reason to exclude that contextual material. Indeed, depending on the context of the article, it may well lend significant support to the submission that readers would have understood the publication to be an expression of opinion."
The words complained of set in context
"Emil Kirkegaard was never 'smeared' by s0-called SJW's since newspapers and other news sources, covering the entire political-spectrum exposed him as a child-rape/paedophilia apologist and neo-Nazi; the Socialist Worker is far-left wing, The Guardian is left wing , The Independent is centrist, The Telegraph is centre-right, while the Daily Mail, right-wing. As for far-right, there is a thread on Stormfront criticising Kirkegaard's obscene child rape comments. It's not a right or left issue, but right or wrong: anyone with a moral conscience can see Kirkegaard is a vile human and paedophile.
And no surprise, it turns out the sick freak Kirkegaard is a fan of animated baby porn and wants it made legal:
https://rationalwiki.org/wiki/Emil_O._W._Kirkegaard#Animated_baby_porn"
"Animated baby porn
Kirkegaard disturbingly supports possession of animated (cartoon) baby pornography, that is illegal in most countries. In 2010, he wrote a blog post defending animated baby/child porn and criticised Sweden and Norway for having laws against it."
"@DFH
He penned an essay defending animated baby-porn and argues for it to be made legal in Norway and Sweden and any other country that has banned it. So he does support legalising it since the vast majority of countries have banned it (Denmark being the only notable exception).
When questioned if he supports possession/legalising of *real* child porn, what did he say?
https://rationalwiki.org/w/index.php?title=Talk:Emil_O._W._Kirkegaard&diff=prev&oldid=1862554
'As for possession, I'm unsure. My blogpost is from 2012, 5 years ago, and I haven't thought much of the topic since.'
What kind of an answer is that? Only something a paedophile would write. A non-paedophile of course is against child porn, but Kirkegaard is ambiguous/undecided and refuses to be against it.
Furthermore, Kirkegaard uses the paedophilia-apologist definition of paedophilia as pre-pubescent:
https://rationalwiki.org/w/index.php?title=Talk:Emil_O._W._Kirkegaard&diff=prev&oldid=1863285
In his essay where he proposes a compromise for paedophiles is to rape children while they sleep, Kirkegaard wrote:
"One can have sex with some rather young ones (say, any consenting child in puberty) without any moral problems."
Children in puberty are as young as 11-12; in other words Kirkegaard literally supports adults having sex with children, who while not pre-pubescent are still under the age of consent.
https://rationalwiki.org/wiki/Emil_O._W._Kirkegaard#Child_rape
Why are you defending a blatant paedophile ?"
a. The first hyperlink led to a comment made by the Claimant on an internet page ('RationalWiki'), in which it appears the Claimant stated the following:
"I think you need more reading comprehension. The idea with legalizing child porn possession was to avoid the creation of blatant internet censorship, which is now is place following the first ban on child porn possession. This idea does not originate with me, but from [http://falkvinge.net/2012/09/07/three-reasons-child-porn-must-be-re-legalized-in-the-coming-decade/ Rick Falkvinge, of the Swedish Pirate Party]. I never proposed the compromise attributed to me, it was a hypothetical. I have public stated that I think the evidence shows that rape and child rape/sexual abuse (CSA) is harmful. For instance,
[http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3482426/ this study] using a MZ twin control method found that even within twin pairs, the association of a history (self-reported) of CSA and mental illness is found, making it likely that the association is causal. My remark was simply that if you have sex with someone while they are asleep and somehow don't wake up from it and they never discover it later somehow, it is not likely for there to be any causal effects on mental health. How would there be? As for 'my' definition of pedophilia, it is totally in line with mainstream research, as anyone can easily verify [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pedophilia by reading Wikipedia]. For the record, I'm not in favor of lowering the age of consent from the current Danish value of 15, nor do I propose legalizing the filming of child porn. As for possession, I'm unsure. My blogpost is from 2012, 5 years ago, and I haven't thought much of the topic since. In fact, I have posted a total of [http://emilkirkegaard.dk/en/?s=pedo&submit=Search 2 times on pedophilia], out of some 940 blogposts (as of writing). --[[User:EmilOWK|EmilOWK]] ([[User talk:EmilOWK|talk]]) 23:47, 24 August 2017 (UTC)"
b. The second hyperlink led to a comment made by the Claimant on a RationalWiki page, in which the Claimant stated the following in response to an edit made on the site:
"== "Interestingly, Kirkegaard narrowly defines pedophilia as adult-prepubescent sex, which excludes teens who're still under the age of consent." ==
There is nothing particularly interesting about this. As [https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs11194-007-9049-0 Blanchard et al 2007] note:
:The term pedophilia may be defined as the erotic orientation of persons whose sexual attraction to prepubescent children exceeds their sexual attraction to pubescent or physically mature persons (Freund 1981). Similarly, the term hebephilia (Glueck 1955) refers to persons who are most attracted to pubescent children, and the term teleiophilia (Blanchard et al. 2000), to persons who are most attracted to physically mature adults. Although most authorities are careful to define pedophilia in terms of erotic interest in prepubescent children (e.g., DSM-IV-TR; American Psychiatric Association 2000), the distinction between pedophilia and hebephilia is somewhat artificial. Many child molesters—sometimes called pedohebephiles (Freund et al. 1972)—approach both prepubescent and pubescent children. Such patterns of offending correspond with the realities of physical maturation. The external body shape changes gradually and continuously from childhood though puberty, adolescence, and maturity. Even the single most discrete, watershed event in either sex—menarche in females—produces no abrupt change in the individual's outward appearance.
This article is not particularly unusual in its use of these terms, as can be seen by reading [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pedophilia Wikipedia] and [https://scholar.google.dk/scholar?q=pedophilia+hebephilia&btnG=&hl=en&as_sdt=0%2C31 searching for the terms on Google Scholar]. The current text makes it seem like I made up/cherry-picked some especially narrow definition for nefarious purposes, while in actual fact I'm using the most common definition. --[[User:EmilOWK|EmilOWK]] ([[User talk:EmilOWK|talk]]) 10:48, 26 August 2017 (UTC)"
c. The third hyperlink led to an article about the Claimant which stated the following:
"Paedophilia controversies
Child rape
'Emil Kirkegaard, who has written supportively of paedophiles being allowed to have 'sex with a sleeping child'.
—Sophia Siddiqui, Institute of Race Relations
Kirkegaard has been described in mainstream and other news sources as a child-rape apologist, defender of paedophilia, and a paedophilehimself. This comes from a 2012 blog post in which he makes a sickening compromise for paedophiles - to rape children while they sleep:
'Perhaps a compromise is having sex with a sleeping child without them knowing it (so, using sleeping medicine). If they dont[sic] notice it is difficult to see how they cud[sic] be harmed, even if it is rape.'
In the same blog post, Kirkegaard defends paedophilia, by writing:
'One can have sex with some rather young ones (say, any consenting child in puberty) without any moral problems.'
Children in puberty are as young as 11-12; in other words Kirkegaard literally supports adults having sex with children, who while not pre-pubescent are still under the age of consent.
In response to newspapers (e.g. The Guardian) quoting his post and describing him as paedophilia apologist, Kirkegaard updated it in January 2018, claiming his post was only a 'thought experiment'. However, this was never mentioned originally and looks like damage control to his reputation.
In August 2017, when questioned about his compromise for paedophiles to rape sleeping children, Kirkegaard defended his original statement and said he thinks there will be no mental harm:
'My remark was simply that if you have sex with someone [children] while they are asleep and somehow don't wake up from it and they never discover it later somehow, it is not likely for there to be any causal effects on mental health. How would there be ?'
—Emil Kirkegaard, child rape apologist"
Animated baby porn
Kirkegaard disturbingly supports possession of animated (cartoon) baby pornography, that is illegal in most countries. In 2010, he wrote a blog post defending animated baby/child porn and criticised Sweden and Norway for having laws against it."
"Kirkegaard supports possession of animated child porn and wants to legalise it for the countries he said it was banned in, which is virtually all countries – so it's the same thing to describe him as a 'fan of animated baby porn'. The point is: only paedophiles support possession of CP [child pornography] or cartoon baby porn. If Kirkegaard isn't a paedophile, why is he pro-CP? Why would a non-paedophile want to legalise obscene cartoons of babies being raped in diapers? Please do care to explain…. Like I said, it's obvious to anyone, Kirkegaard is a paedophile. This is why all mainstream newspapers described him as either a paedophile-apologist or paedophile. And these journalists independently read Kirkegaard's comments and came to the same conclusion as myself. The only people denying this are some neo-Nazi nutjobs on this weird website because you share Kirkegaard's cranky/pseudo-scientific views on race.
He never posted paedophiles should be castrated, what he said was this:
'the best solution to one who is exclusively aroused by very young children: castration, either medical or fysical. This will help reduce libido.'
He's added 'very' there when this was not mentioned earlier, so is talking here of infants or pre-pubescent. In the same post he says there are no moral issues for adults to have sex with 'rather young ones' in puberty, so he's distinguishing children in puberty to pre-pubescent's; he's fine for adults to have sex with children in puberty under age of consent, but not pre-pubescent. Both though are paedophilia. Kirkegaard though restricts the term paedophilia to only pre-pubescent's. This is what paedophilia-apologists do to try to normalise having sex with children in puberty but below age of consent.
This is all explained on the RW article.
And if you're claiming I 'smeared' Kirkegaard, are you saying every mainstream journalist/newspaper has as well ?"
The parties' contentions
The Defendant's case
a. the Claimant has controversial opinions on the acceptability of paedophilia due to his own writings in support of child rape; and
b. the Claimant is a weird and vindictive individual due to his conduct in repeatedly smearing and attacking the Defendant on the Claimant's website.
The Claimant's submissions
Discussion
The context and the hyper-linked material
Fact v opinion, and the meaning of the Posts
a. It offers a conclusion or inference reached by the Defendant that the Claimant's own writings show that he supports paedophilia and child rape;
b. It predicts for the future, based on how the Defendant has perceived the Claimant to have acted in the past, how he will react were such a thing to happen;
c. 'Sick creep' is obviously a form of (fairly severe) criticism, bordering on vulgar abuse by the Defendant of the Claimant. But Twitter is a medium where people abuse each other regularly and not in a literal way, and a reasonable reader would know that.
a. That the Claimant's own writings demonstrate that he supports child rape and supports paedophila;
b. That anyone making such an observation can anticipate being the subject of retaliation or unspecified vindictive behaviour but, presumably, online abuse such is the nature of the Claimant's unpleasant character.
a. The clear identification of the Claimant as the subject of the Post;
b. The Defendant was responding by way of counter-argument to an assertion that Mr Karlin had advanced that the Claimant had been the victim of misplaced criticism ('smear') by 'social justice warriors'. Thus, the ordinary reasonable reader would have understood this Post to have been a contribution to an on-going debate;
c. The Defendant set out the basis for his opinion that Mr Karlin was wrong in that view, namely, that the Claimant had been 'exposed' as a paedophile by a range of publications across the political spectrum from the far-left to the far-right;
d. The words complained of were a deduction from what had been previously stated: because publications of all shades of politics had reached the same conclusion about the Claimant, the issue was not one of left-right politics, and all were agreed that the Claimant is a paedophile, a view point supported by the hyper-linked article which further supported that view;
e. The Post in part involves criticising that which the Claimant had written and imputing a point of view to him based on his writings about child pornography and that it ought to be lawful.
a. The Claimant is an apologist for paedophilia;
b. Any right-thinking person would regard him as vile and a paedophile;
c. He is in favour of animated pornography involving babies, supports possession of it which he considers ought to be lawful, and has published material that is critical of Sweden and Norway for having laws against it.
a. Post 3 is a direct response to a comment made by another user in the thread, @DFH. The ordinary reasonable reader would therefore have understood this Post to be part of an argument/dispute with another user intended to refute and respond by way of argument to the counter-argument put by @DFH including that the Defendant had lied about the Claimant's view on paedophilia;
b. The Post consisted of a response by the Defendant to a body of writings by the Claimant on the topic of paedophilia;
c. The words complained of came at the end of the post in the course of which the Defendant had cited a number of hyperlinked sources to support his inferred conclusion that the Claimant blatantly supports paedophile;
d. The Defendant had noted the ambiguities in the Claimant's writings about child pornography. Although he had written an essay defending animated child pornography and had argued for it to be made legal in Norway and Sweden, he had also given an ambivalent response to whether the possession of non-animated child pornography should be illegal, as directly linked to in the first hyperlink in Post 3;
e. The Defendant inferred from some of the Claimant's writings a viewpoint he describes as being 'paedophilia apologist;'
f. The third hyperlinked article, which referred to other sources as having noted the Claimant's support for paedophilia;
g. In addition to the above, the reader of the words complained of would have also read the preceding thread and would have been aware of the additional evidence adduced by the Defendant in Post Two, as well as the general context that underpinned the online debate.
a. The Claimant supports legalising baby pornography because he has written an essay defending animated baby pornography;
b. The Claimant is a paedophile apologist because he expressed himself not to have thought about it for some years when asked if he supported possession or legalisation of it, whereas a non-paedophile apologist would have been unquestionably against it;
c. The Claimant has adopted arguments which those who apologise for paedophilia utilise;
d. The Claimant supports the right of adults to have sex with children under the age of consent and that he believes that raping children whilst they sleep would not cause harm;
a. Post 1 is a direct response to a comment made @DFH. This comment by @DFH was made in direct response to Post 3, and Post 1 essentially clarifies the Defendant's remarks in Post 3 in the face of challenge by @DFH. The ordinary reasonable reader would therefore have understood this Post to be part of the on-going argument between @DFH and the Defendant.
b. In a similar manner to Posts 2 and 3 above, I consider the Defendant to be setting out what is clearly an inferred opinion that the Claimant is an apologist for paedophilia, and provides further evidence in support besides that in Posts 2 and 3 which the hypothetical reader would already have read.
c. That the words complained of are an expression of opinion is highlighted by the prefatory words, 'Like I said, it's obvious to anyone …' and the fact that the Defendant supports his opinion by reference to what he considers to be the viewpoint of all mainstream media outlets.
a. The Claimant supports the possession of animated child pornography and wishes to see it legalised and is a paedophile;
b. His writings concerning pubescent and pre-pubescent children, and the distinction that he draws, supports the viewpoint that he is a paedophilia apologist.