BAILII is celebrating 24 years of free online access to the law! Would you
consider making a contribution?
No donation is too small. If every visitor before 31 December gives just £1, it
will have a significant impact on BAILII's ability to continue providing free
access to the law.
Thank you very much for your support!
[New search]
[Printable PDF version]
[Help]
Genetic Models of Disease Resistance in
Livestock: “What Does Our Conscience Want?”
Kenneth M Boyd
Table of Contents:
|
Cite as:
K M Boyd, "Genetic Models of Disease Resistance in
Livestock: “What Does Our Conscience Want?”", (2008) 5:1 SCRIPT-ed
161 @:
http://www.law.ed.ac.uk/ahrc/script-ed/vol5-1/boyd.asp
Download options |
|
|
DOI: 10.2966/scrip.050108.161 |
|
© Kenneth M Boyd 2008.
This work is licensed under a
Creative Commons Licence.
Please click on the link to read the terms and conditions.
|
1. Introduction
‘What does our
conscience want?’
Conscience is the
process of reflecting on the morality of our actions and intentions:
are they right or wrong, good or bad? The word ‘conscience’
literally means ‘knowing together,’ and it is sometimes
compared to a court of law – an ‘inner court’ –
where all the evidence and arguments about the morality of an action
or intention are brought together for review and judgement. In that
inner court, what most people want to hear is the verdict ‘not
guilty.’ They want to be declared ‘innocent,’ or to
have what in English is called a ‘clear’ conscience.
2. Conscience and Honesty
There are several
reasons why that verdict may be difficult to pronounce. Although
conscience may be like a court of law, it is a court in which the
prosecutor, defender and judge are all the same person, and where the
equivalent to a jury – all the people whose moral views and
arguments we have heard from childhood to today – often speak
with different and, especially in a modern pluralistic society,
conflicting voices. With no authoritative and impartial judge, and a
divided jury, the chances of achieving a ‘clear’
conscience are diminished. To be ‘clear,’ conscience has
to be clear that all the evidence and arguments about the morality of
an action or intention have been brought to light and judged
impartially. But this, I suggest, can be difficult for the
self-judging conscience to achieve: important issues may be ignored
or fudged in the interest of self-justification, or minor issues may
be exaggerated by over-scrupulous self-accusation. Honesty about
oneself, in other words, is not easy.
In this context, a
religious or philosophical belief that there is an ultimate judge or
are absolute standards before whom or which actions and intentions
must be judged, can be a strong incentive to be as honest as
possible. But what the ultimate judge or absolute standards actually
require in particular circumstances is still often a matter of
interpretation on which different authorities disagree; and even when
it seems clear that certain actions or intentions are wrong, the
desire to be honest about whether or not one has avoided them, may
obscure other issues equally important for conscience to consider. As
noted above, what most people want, whatever their beliefs, is to be
declared ‘innocent’ by conscience. ‘Innocent’
literally means ‘not causing harm,’ and the immediate
thought is ‘not causing harm by one’s action.’ But
while we may directly cause harm by ‘the things we have done
that we ought not to have done,’ harm may also come about in
the space left by the ‘things we have left undone that we ought
to have done.’ To be clear, insofar as that is ever possible,
conscience needs to be clear, not only about the benefits and harm
which may flow from a particular action performed or proposed, but
also about the cost, to others, of maintaining its own ‘innocence’
or integrity.
3. Conscience and Animal Health
Applying these
considerations to the subject of genetic models of disease resistance
in livestock, it could be argued that research into ways of improving
animal health surely is something of which our conscience should
approve, and that moral scruples about genetic modification should
not be allowed to get in the way of achieving this beneficent goal.
If it was just as ethically simple as that however – that the
end justifies the means – the question of what our conscience
wants could be easily settled. But the ethical issues, I suggest, are
more complicated, not only because the end aimed at by research has
major implications for ‘food safety, the economy of the sector
and human health’ as well as ‘animal welfare,’ but
also because the means, techniques of genetic modification, raise
ethical questions which go beyond mere moral scruples.
Whether the inclusion
of ‘food safety, the economy of the sector and human health’
makes the end less or more deserving of conscience’s approval,
is debateable. But for the present purpose, let us assume that
improving animal health and welfare, or more specifically increasing
disease resistance in farm animals, is the end in relation to which
ethical questions about the means should be considered. A question
which then immediately arises, however, is whether increasing disease
resistance in farm animals is the same as improving their health and
welfare.
‘Health’ is
a tricky concept to define, at least in humans, particularly when it
is seen as more than the absence of disease, or as ‘positive’
health. If, moreover, you examine how the word has come to be used
about humans, it seems to be especially associated with youth,
physical strength or athleticism and sexual vigour, characteristics
carried over perhaps from the idea of a breeding animal at the peak
of its performance. But how healthy actually is a top-flight athlete,
not just at the moment of bursting the tape, but in terms that are
sustainable? Being healthy can mean having the physical and mental
resources to recover from being ill, or from being just plain
exhausted, resources which might be prematurely drained if, never
feeling ill or exhausted, we dashed about all the time with the
boundless enthusiasm of Labrador Retrievers.
Relating this back to
the more bovine health therefore, it may be difficult to entirely
separate the idea of animal health from what we want farm animals to
be healthy for, namely to produce food for human consumption. I’m
not here conjuring up the image of Beltsville pigs, where as I
understand it the aim was not health but productivity. But for our
conscience to be clear, I suggest, the aim of increasing disease
resistance in livestock must be one in which animal
health-for-human-purposes is not incompatible with animal welfare, or
health-for-their-own-sake. An obvious example is not seeking to
increase livestock’s resistance to diseases which could equally
be avoided by practical improvements in their environment and
husbandry. A more problematic example would be if ‘a shorter
life but a happier one’ was the result of increased disease
resistance.
These may be questions
on which a vet is better qualified to judge than an ethicist. But
within the broad ethical formula I’ve suggested – that
the end of increasing disease resistance in livestock must be one in
which animal health-for-human-purposes is not incompatible with
animal welfare, or health-for-their-own-sake – what about the
means?
By genetic
modification?
4. Conscience, Scientists and Genetic
Modification of Animals
Genetic modification
raises a variety of ethical questions. These include those concerned
with the unpredictability of what is sometimes called
‘biological engineering,’ but differs from other forms of
engineering in significant ways. As Hans Jonas once put it, there is:
… an important difference in “engineering”
procedure. With hardware, the maker is the sole agent vis-à-vis
the passive material. With organisms, the modifier is co-agent with
the self-acting material, viz., the biological system, into whose
self-activity he inserts the new fractional determinant, to be
integrated into the totality of its autonomous determinants by their
own working… This affects the important issue of
predictability. In hardware engineering, the number of “unknowns”
is practically nil, and the engineer can accurately predict the
properties of his product. For the biological engineer, who has to
take over “sight-unseen”, the untold complexity of the
given determinants with their self-functioning dynamics, the number
of unknowns in the design is immense. To them he must commit his
contributory share in the totality of causes. Prediction of its fate
is thus reduced to guessing, planning – to gambling.1
Now Jonas wrote that in
the late 1960s or early 1970s, and it might be argued that scientific
experience of genetic modification and European adoption of the
‘precautionary principle’ has since made ‘biological
engineering’ much safer and less unpredictable. But a well
reasoned paper on genetically modified organisms, published in 2007,2
suggests that ‘within risk assessment’ it is still the
case that ‘scientific uncertainties are poorly integrated;’3
and while some forms of genetic modification may pose fewer risks to
humans, animals or the environment, than others do, it would be a
bold scientist, I think, who could claim that any experiment in
genetic modification was entirely risk-free, or that the measures
taken to prevent harm resulting from it were infallible.
What does this say to
the conscience of the scientist? Some might say that genetic
modification is just too risky to proceed with any further. Not only
is it interfering with Nature, it also sets us on a slippery slope
(i.e.: to the nightmare world of Margaret Atwood’s Oryx and
Crake, in which ‘ChickieNobs,’ chickens which have
been genetically modified and decerebrated, thereby solving the
problem of food supply and animal suffering at a stroke, escape into
the environment, together with ‘pigoons,’ vicious pigs
who are also fiendishly clever because they have been genetically
modified with human genes in order to produce organs for humans).4
How does the
scientist’s conscience respond to that kind of warning? One
thing to note, perhaps, is that arguments about not interfering with
Nature often presuppose, without examining too closely, the idea that
left to itself, Nature has its own ways of maintaining or
re-establishing ecological stability. But while there is some general
truth to that, it also avoids the question of humanity’s role
and history as part of Nature, and also the fact that human
survival has always depended – and because Nature is never
finally stable, always will depend – on interfering in some way
with the rest of Nature. This suggests therefore that the question
for the scientists’ conscience is not whether, but how, it is
right to interfere, and how to avoid sliding down the slippery slope.
In the case of genetic modification of animals, there are at least
three things that the scientist’s conscience needs to consider:
the risks and
burdens of the intervention in relation to the purpose for which it
is proposed;
their own
relationship to and responsibility for genetically modified animals;
sharing their aims
and uncertainties with the wider public.
First, the risks and
burdens of the intervention in relation to the purpose for which it
is proposed. The risks of genetic modification are already assessed
by legislators and regulators in terms of the, albeit variable,
interpretations of the precautionary principle, and the burdens to
animals are weighed against the purposes in the cost-benefit
appraisals of well-regulated animal research. But for scientists to
have as clear a conscience as possible, and to assist regulators in
making what are always judgements, they need to see these
issues not as a matter of getting something past the ethics committee
or the regulator, but in the light of their own individual and
collective conscientious judgement.
Another recent paper
encouragingly suggests how this already happens.5
In the Netherlands, a sample of ‘35 persons from the practice
of biomedical research who are directly involved in genetic
engineering (scientists, biotechnicians, animal caretakers and
laboratory animal scientists)’ were presented with a list of
‘applications of genetic engineering’ and asked to say of
which they disapproved, were neutral, or approved. Unsurprisingly,
given their work, none disapproved of ‘genetic engineering
within scientific research.’ But from a longer list: 23%
disapproved of ‘genetic modification of goats so that they
produce spider silk material in their milk that can be used to
produce stitching materials;’ 36% disapproved of ‘increasing
the capacity of pigs to digest the phosphorus in their food,
resulting in reduced phosphate content of their manure’ (a
contribution to environmental protection); 57% disapproved of
increasing the production and reducing the fat content of pork; 85%
disapproved of (a theoretical case reminiscent of Atwood’s
‘ChickieNobs’) ‘removing all properties of laying
hens that are unnecessary for laying eggs, including their
sentience;’ and 97% disapproved of making hens blind as a
solution to the problem of feather pecking.’ Interestingly,
for the present purpose, 54% disapproved, 20% were neutral and only
23% approved of ‘increasing the resistance of pigs to
production-related diseases.’6
How fine is the line between that ‘increasing the resistance
of pigs to production-related diseases’ and ‘increasing
disease resistance in farm animals’?
Some other questions
asked in this study bring us to the second thing I suggested that the
scientist’s conscience should consider: their own relationship
to and responsibility for genetically modified animals. These asked
if the respondents endorsed the concept of animals’ ‘intrinsic
value.’ Presented with the statements “Animals do not
only have instrumental value, i.e., they are not only valuable
as means to our ends” and “Animals ought never to be
treated solely as means,” 86% and 80% respectively fully agreed
and none strongly disagreed. Moreover, 63% strongly agreed, and 29%
agreed, with the statement that “Genetic engineering
contributes to the instrumentalisation of animals, i.e., the
ever increasing adaptation of animals to our needs and interests.”
While this may sound somewhat inconsistent coming from people
‘directly involved in genetic engineering,’ part of the
reason why they were able to agree with the statement was that many
of them argued that:
not every genetic modification interferes with the identity of the
animal. In their view, only the modifications that cause significant
changes in the appearance and/or the behaviour of the animals should
be regarded as an interference with their identity and therefore as a
violation of animal integrity.7
This stance may also
reflect the experience that these respondents personally had of the
individual genetically modified animals in their own laboratories. I
realise that it is possible to be sentimental about animals,
especially appealing ones like the late Dolly the sheep, but I am
also aware that many people in animal laboratories, like many
farmers, do care about as well as care for their
animals.
In ethical terms,
another author argues, ‘we have an obligation to tend to the
interests of the beings that we create.’ This is most obvious
in the case of children. But although we do not create them, we also
have special obligations to pets for example; and in the case of
vulnerable creatures, which would not have come into the kind of
existence they have without genetic modification, there are
‘obligations to which we are bound because we have taken
them on ourselves, because we have created these beings.’8
The
‘instrumentalisation’ of animals, whether in research or
modified as a result of research, treating them as things,
bio-machines existing solely as means to our ends, is a real moral
risk of biotechnology, especially when all the interest is at the
molecular level. The conscientious remedy for this however, is not to
abandon the whole project of genetic modification, thereby possibly
failing to do the things we ought to do, out of fear of doing the
things we ought not to do. It is rather, to be discriminating about
which things we ought and ought not to do, and in deciding this to be
guided in part by the special obligations we take on ourselves to
care for vulnerable creatures, which would not have come into the
kind of existence they have without our creating them.
5.
Conclusions
Though my emphasis has
been on the conscience of scientists, a word needs to be said about
another element that I suggested conscience should consider, namely
its extension from scientists to the wider public. To this end let me
briefly summarise the main argument of a paper on genetically
modified organisms mentioned above.9
This paper is chiefly concerned with GM crops, but it argues that
public attitudes to biotechnology generally, including the genetic
modification of animals, have to be seen in the context of a ‘complex
of concerns,’ ‘environmental, agricultural,
socio-economic and ethical,’ which have emerged over the past
50 years, with growing public awareness, not always accurate, of what
biotechnology is achieving and aiming to achieve, and with growing
public distrust ‘in scientific institutions and expert systems’
which ‘reduce the complexity of the GMO issue to a solely
scientific risk-based problem.’ As a remedy for this lack of
trust, the authors take a metaphorical cue from Jane Austen’s
novel Sense and Sensibility. The novel:
… describes the lives of two sisters, Marianna and Elinor.
On the surface, these sisters seemingly represent two opposite poles.
Marianna’s emotional and romantic nature represents the cult of
“Sensibility,” whereas Elinor’s rationality
represents the cult of “Sense.” However, just as much as
the two sisters are next of kin, their natures/characters continually
co-construct each other. The sisters thus symbolise a continuous and
complex process of “giving sense to sensibility,” in
which simultaneously “sensibility guides the making of sense.”10
Rational Elinor and
emotional Marianna, these authors suggest, can be compared to the
scientific community and public opinion. The only difference is that
science and the public do not communicate with one another in the
‘co-constructive’ manner of the two sisters, and perhaps
this must change.
Scientific attempts in
the late 20th century to tell people ‘the facts’
about science, in the belief that if these were understood, the
public would approve of biotechnology, failed to stem the tide of
distrust. But the more recent model of ‘public engagement with
science’ may be more promising. If the various shades of public
sensibility are allowed greater participation in decision-making,
particularly about risk assessment, public sensibility will need the
help of scientific sense in order to make sense of the problems
involved. By sharing not only its aims, but also its uncertainties
and its decision-making with public sensibility, in other words, the
scientific community may find a way of answering the question ‘What
does our conscience want?’ that is more robust and reliable in
the long run.
*
Professor of Medical Ethics, College of Medicine and Veterinary
Medicine, University of Edinburgh.
1
H Jonas, Philosophical Essays from Ancient Creed to Technological
Man (1974), at 143.
2
Y Devos et al., “Ethics in the Societal Debate on
Genetically Modified Organisms: A (Re)Quest for Sense and
Sensibility” (2007) Journal of Agricultural and
Environmental Ethics (DOI 10.1007/s10806-007-9057-6)
4
M Atwood, Oryx and Crake (2003). Incidentally, when I read
the novel, I thought it rather far-fetched, but it is widely cited
as a warning in a respectable academic paper published last year on
‘ethical dimensions of the genetic engineering of animals for
human consumption,’ see T Warkentin, “Dis/integrating
Animals: Ethical Dimensions of the Genetic Engineering of Animals
for Human Consumption” (2006) 20 AI & Soc, 82-102.
5
R de Vries, “Ethical Concepts Regarding the Genetic
Engineering of Laboratory Animals” (2006) 9 Medicine,
Health Care and Philosophy, 211-225.
8
B Hale, “The Moral Considerability of Invasive Transgenic
Animals” (2006) 19 Journal of Agricultural and
Environmental Ethics, 337-366.
9
Y Devos et al., note 2.
BAILII:
Copyright Policy |
Disclaimers |
Privacy Policy |
Feedback |
Donate to BAILII
URL: http://www.bailii.org/uk/other/journals/Script-ed/2008/5_1_SCRIPT-ed_161.html